I.1.7a
12/21/20
Okay, I finally summoned the bravery to chip away at the 4-part 1.7. Well, at least part (a). And things actually
proceeded quite smoothly... until I had an existential crisis, as you'll see.
We have to show that the following are equivalent:
(i) X is Noetherian (i.e. satisfies the desending chain condition on closed sets)
(ii) every nonempty family of closed subsets of X has a minimal element
(iii) X satisfies the ascending chain condition for open subsets
(iv) every nonempty family of open subsets of X has a maximal element
Taking a glance at it, it looks to me like
(i) (iii) (iv) (ii) (i) is the easiest order.
(i) (iii) is trivial. Just take complements.
I'll leave (iii) (iv) for last.
(iv) (ii) is also an easy "complements" argument
Let's show (ii) (i):
Given a descending chain
| (1) |
of closed subsets of X.
Let L = {Ci}i=1∞. L has a minimal element Cn, by (ii). I.e. Cn ⊃ CjCn = Cj. In particular,
Cn = Cn+1 = Cn+2 = , so we're done.
Okay, so everything is done except (iii) (iv) (which is kind of the converse of (ii) (i), just the open set
version).
Let L be a collection of open subsets of X. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that L does not have a maximal
element. i.e.
| (2) |
Pick an arbitrary element V 1 ∈ L to begin a chain.
Suppose we already have a chain
| (3) |
Then using the maximality property, there is a V n+1 ∈ L such that V n ⊂ V n+1. Hence we can add this to the
chain:
| (4) |
Now, the handwavy thing to say would be, this process makes an infinite ascending proper chain of open subsets,
contradicting (iii), and we'd be done.
Are you ready for some trippy stuff? Okay.
Something seems off with the reasoning to me. Do we really get an infinite chain? What I provided above was an
inductive proof: For any natural number n, there is a chain
| (5) |
I.e. I can construct chains of arbitrary finite length. I can make n as big as I want and extend the chain to that
amount. But how does that translate to an infinite chain. Intuitively it seems like it would work, but I can't find a
mathematical justification for it. And the ascending chain condition seems to always be stated in terms of infinite
chains.
(Punchline: the "existential" crisis I was referring to at the start was regarding to the existence of the
infinite chain, which is nevertheless more troubling than screaming "WHY DO I EX1ST!?!?111?!!?" to
myself)
I understand that I am making infinitely many choices, but what I'm doing here seems to require MORE than just
using the axiom of Choice. The axiom of Choice allows me to pick one element per a collection of sets, right?
But for Choice, that collection is presumably predetermined. The choices I'm making here aren't from a
predetermined collection of sets, because in my proof, each choice DEPENDS ON THE LAST CHOICE. That seems
worse than pure Choice.
So the question remains: How finite chains of arbitrary length extend to an infinite chain, especially when each finite
chain depends on the last?
UPDATE: I just looked up several proofs, and they're pretty much verbatim to mine. I.e., they just assume
that an infinite chain exists by the inductive logic. One of them mentions Choice, but like I said, that
doesn't seem sufficient. I'm not convinced. I know it seems intuitive, but I can't wrap my head around
it.
UPDATE: Okay, after like an hour or two of thinking about it, in desperation, I literally looked up "axiom of
dependent choice", and it exists. This precisely solves my problem. I was asking, "how does an arbitrary
finite length chain, where the choice of each chain depedns on the last, extend to an infinite length chain?" And, as
it states,
Even without such an axiom, for any n, one can use ordinary mathematical induction to form the first n terms of such a sequence. The axiom of dependent choice says that we can form a whole (countably infinite) sequence this way.